For a more extensive analysis of text no. 4 than what appears in this post, see my Actus essendi and the Habit of the First Principle in Thomas Aquinas (New York: Einsiedler Press, 2019), 93-97.
Commentary on
In III Sententiarum, distinction 11, question 1, article 2, ad 2
In this article Aquinas asks whether Christ can be said to be creatura. In the answer to the question Aquinas structures an argument based on the primary signification of the analogous term esse.
With the expression simpliciter et per se (and its opposite secundum quid et per accidens) Aquinas
emphasizes that the primary meaning of the term esse refers to the esse
that belongs to the subsisting suppositum.
Aquinas explains that esse can be said to belong to the form—forma—because the subsisting suppositum is essentially composed of matter and form; and for the same reason, esse can be said to belong to matter. In the material world, matter and form are the essential principles of a subsisting suppositum, that is, the composite.
Similarly, esse can be said to belong to accidents because accidents inhere in the subsisting suppositum.
Thus when esse is said of a form, or when esse is said of matter, or when esse is said of accidents, esse is said in a qualified sense. Only of the subsisting suppositum is esse affirmed simpliciter et per se.
It is only because of the relation of matter, form, and accidents to the esse of the subsisting suppositum that matter, form, and accidents can be said to possess esse in a qualified sense.
Aquinas explains that esse can be said to belong to the form—forma—because the subsisting suppositum is essentially composed of matter and form; and for the same reason, esse can be said to belong to matter. In the material world, matter and form are the essential principles of a subsisting suppositum, that is, the composite.
Similarly, esse can be said to belong to accidents because accidents inhere in the subsisting suppositum.
Thus when esse is said of a form, or when esse is said of matter, or when esse is said of accidents, esse is said in a qualified sense. Only of the subsisting suppositum is esse affirmed simpliciter et per se.
It is only because of the relation of matter, form, and accidents to the esse of the subsisting suppositum that matter, form, and accidents can be said to possess esse in a qualified sense.
The esse of the subsisting suppositum is said to come into existence per modum creationis. But the esse of the quiddity (which is the
material nature composed of matter and form) and the esse of accidents, are said to come into existence per modum informationis.
According to Aquinas, Aristotle postulated that the world always existed with a constant uninterrupted flow of generation and corruption of things, and that it was through such beginningless and endless chain of perishable pre-existing materials that Aristotle understood how things come into existence in the visible world per modum informationis.
While preserving some elements of such conception of the world, Aquinas understood things differently, since for Aquinas a subsisting suppositum ultimately comes into existence per modum creationis.
According to Aquinas, Aristotle postulated that the world always existed with a constant uninterrupted flow of generation and corruption of things, and that it was through such beginningless and endless chain of perishable pre-existing materials that Aristotle understood how things come into existence in the visible world per modum informationis.
While preserving some elements of such conception of the world, Aquinas understood things differently, since for Aquinas a subsisting suppositum ultimately comes into existence per modum creationis.
Now in the case of human beings,
the simpliciter et per se meaning of esse refers to the esse of the person.
Thus, the affirmation Christus est signifies the personal esse of Christ, not the esse of His nature, nor the esse of His accidents, and certainly not the esse of any of the essential principles of His Most Holy Humanity, all of which can be said to possess esse only in a qualified sense.
Thus, the affirmation Christus est signifies the personal esse of Christ, not the esse of His nature, nor the esse of His accidents, and certainly not the esse of any of the essential principles of His Most Holy Humanity, all of which can be said to possess esse only in a qualified sense.
The union of the divine nature
and the human nature takes place in only one suppositum which is the divine
suppositum, the only suppositum that Christ has. In Christ there is no human suppositum. In Christ there is no human
person.
Christ is only one person, the Second Person of the Most Blessed Trinity, the person in whom the hypostatic union of two natures, the human and the divine, takes place.
Christ is only one person, the Second Person of the Most Blessed Trinity, the person in whom the hypostatic union of two natures, the human and the divine, takes place.
Therefore, Christ cannot be said
to be creatura. The esse of Christ is only one, that is, the
divine, uncreated esse.
Christ is not creatura, but just as esse can be said in a qualified sense of matter, form, and accidents, some things that belong to Christ can be said to be created.
Christ is not creatura, but just as esse can be said in a qualified sense of matter, form, and accidents, some things that belong to Christ can be said to be created.
Thus Aquinas writes:
“Respondeo dicendum, quod creatio
proprie respicit esse rei: unde dicitur in lib. De causis, quod esse est per creationem, alia vero per
informationem. Esse autem simpliciter et per se est suppositi subsistentis;
alia vero dicuntur esse, inquantum suppositum in eis subsistit, vel
essentialiter, sicut materia et forma, et sic natura ipsa dicitur esse; vel
accidentaliter, sicut accidentia dicuntur esse. Esse ergo dictum simpliciter de
supposito significat esse personale ipsius; esse vero, secundum quod convenit
parti vel accidenti, non dicitur simpliciter de supposito, sed suppositum dicitur
esse in eo; unde cum dico: ‘Christus est,’ significatur esse ipsius, non autem
esse ipsius naturae, vel accidentis, vel partis. Cum autem fiat unio naturarum
in esse suppositi secundum secundam opinionem, esse, secundum quod Christus
simpliciter esse dicitur, est esse increatum; unde non potest dici creatura,
non tantum ad evitandum errorem Arii, ut quidam dicunt, sed etiam ad vitandum
falsitatem. Potest tamen dici, quod aliquid creatum est in Christo, scilicet
humana natura; quia esse quamvis sit unum, tamen respectum habet ad naturam et
ad partes ejus, secundum quas humana natura dicitur esse in Christo, vel partes
aut accidentia ejus, ut supra, dist. 6, dictum est. Unde sicut esse aliquo modo
ad naturam pertinet, et ad partes et accidentia ejus, ita et creatio” (In III Sententiarum, distinction 11,
question 1, article 2, corpus).
With this background Aquinas proceeds
to respond to the following objection: When there are lower categories contained in
a higher category, things that are contained in a lower category are also
contained in the higher one. Now the category of man—homo, and several other categories, belong to the wider category of creatura. Therefore, if we affirm that
Christ is man—homo, as we do when we confess our faith, we should also affirm that Christ
is creatura.
To this objection Aquinas responds
with a flat negation of the assumption that creatura is a wider category than the
category of man—homo. One
reason is that what comes into existence per
modum creationis is the esse of
the subsisting suppositum, not its quiddity. Now the esse of the subsisting supposita do not generate a category or
genus as their quidditas does: what is common to things contained in a category
or genus is their quiddity, not their esse.
Or better explained, the intellectual conception expressed by the term creatura cannot be said to be superior to the intellectual conception expressed by the term man—homo—on account of the way these conceptions relate to the quiddity of man.
The activity of creation, Aquinas affirms, does not relate to quiddity except through the actus essendi which is the first, of created things—primus terminus creationis. Therefore, on the side of the quiddity, Christ may be said to have a created humanity. But on the side of the actus essendi, the person of Christ possesses the uncreated actus essendi of God. Therefore the person of Christ cannot be said to come into existence per modum creationis.
Or better explained, the intellectual conception expressed by the term creatura cannot be said to be superior to the intellectual conception expressed by the term man—homo—on account of the way these conceptions relate to the quiddity of man.
The activity of creation, Aquinas affirms, does not relate to quiddity except through the actus essendi which is the first, of created things—primus terminus creationis. Therefore, on the side of the quiddity, Christ may be said to have a created humanity. But on the side of the actus essendi, the person of Christ possesses the uncreated actus essendi of God. Therefore the person of Christ cannot be said to come into existence per modum creationis.
Here is the objection as Aquinas
wrote it, and the response in his own words:
“Praeterea, de quocumque
praedicatur inferius, et superius. Sed creatura est superius ad hominem. Ergo
cum homo praedicetur de Christo, creatura de ipso praedicabitur” (In III Sententiarum, distinction 11,
question 1, article 2, argument 2).
“Ad secundum dicendum, quod creatura
non est superius ad hominem: quia creatio magis respicit esse quam naturam.
Esse autem non est genus, nec inducitur in significatione alicujus generis, ut
dicit Avicenna, cum ea quae sunt in uno genere, non conveniant in uno esse, sed
in natura communi. Vel dicendum, quod creatura non est superius ad hominem,
significans quid est homo: quia creatio non respicit naturam vel essentiam,
nisi mediante actu essendi; qui est primus terminus creationis. Humana autem
natura in Christo non habet aliud esse perfectum, quod est esse hypostasis,
quam esse divinae personae; et ideo, simpliciter loquendo, creatura dici non
potest: quia intelligeretur quod esse perfectum hypostasis Christi per
creationem esset acquisitum” (In III
Sententiarum, distinction 11, question 1, article 2, ad 2).
This text is important because it
explicitly manifests how Aquinas conceived the connection between the notion of
creation and the notion of actus essendi:
(1) “Creatio proprie respicit esse rei,”
and (2) Actus essendi “est primus terminus creationis.”
There is no room for doubt that in this text the res significata of the term actus essendi is the metaphysical principle of actus essendi as instantiated in a subsisting suppositum.