For a more extensive analysis of text no. 12 than what appears in this post, see my Actus essendi and the Habit of the First Principle in Thomas Aquinas (New York: Einsiedler Press, 2019), 160-172.
Commentary on
In IV Metaphysicorum, lecture 2, paragraph no. 6
In his
commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics, Aquinas uses the
expression actus
essendi once, namely, in his commentary
on book IV, lecture 2. The context surrounding the text is an explanation of
why the consideration of the transcendental notion of unum is among the tasks that belong to the discipline of metaphysics. The
analysis shows that the terms ens and unum signify the same reality (convertuntur secundum supposita) but
differ conceptually. The ratio significata of the term ens is different from that of the term unum.
Because extramental subsisting things are composed of quiddity and actus essendi, it is always the case that one and the same extramental subsisting thing is simultaneously habens quidditatem and habens actum essendi.
Aquinas
first argues that ens and unum signify the same reality because ens and unum added to the concept homo (man), or to similar concepts,
cause no difference. Nothing different in reality is expressed with these
affirmations: (1) est
homo, (2) est unus homo, and (3) est
ens homo. (See In IV Metaphysicorum, lecture 2: “Non demonstratur aliquid alterum cum secundum dictionem
replicamus dicendo, est ens homo, et homo, et unus homo.”) But although the terms
ens and unum signify the same reality, Aquinas continues, they are not synonyms. Ens and unum respond to different concepts. It is in the explanation of how the
terms ens and unum differ conceptually that Aquinas introduces the expression actus essendi.
Thus Aquinas writes:
Thus Aquinas writes:
“Sciendum
est enim quod hoc nomen homo, imponitur a quidditate, sive a natura hominis; et
hoc nomen res imponitur a quidditate tantum; hoc vero nomen ens, imponitur ab
actu essendi: et hoc nomen unum, ab ordine vel indivisione. Est enim unum ens
indivisum. Idem autem est quod habet essentiam et quidditatem per illam
essentiam, et quod est in se indivisum. Unde ista tria, res, ens, unum,
significant omnino idem, sed secundum diversas rationes” (In IV Metaphysicorum, lecture 2: For it must be borne in mind that the term homo (man) is derived from the quiddity or the nature of homo (man), and the term res (thing) from the quiddity only; but the term ens is derived from the actus essendi, and the term unum (one) from order or lack of division; for what is unum is an undivided ens. Now what has an essentia, and a quiddity by reason of that essentia, and what is undivided in itself, are the same. Hence these three—res, ens, and unum—signify absolutely the same thing but according to different rationes or concepts.)
For our
purposes this text only confirms once again that for Aquinas the res significata of the term ens is the metaphysical principle of actus essendi.
But for
the sake of completion I shall report here that the context in which this text occurs
also shows how Aquinas distanced himself from Avicenna on the doctrine of the
transcendentals. On this point Jan A. Aertsen’s observations are worth quoting
in detail.
In his
book Medieval Philosophy and the
Transcendentals: The Case of Thomas Aquinas ([Leiden : E. J. Brill, 1996], 192-198) Aertsen
writes:
“Thomas
takes issue with Avicenna especially in texts where he deals with the
transcendentals, since Avicenna’s understanding of being has far-reaching
consequences for the doctrine of the communia. The
most important text is Thomas’s commentary on Metaphysics IV.2,
a text in which a central question of the scientia communis is raised: the question concerning the per se
accidents of being (cf. 3.6.). A crucial role is played in the discussion by
the notion ‘thing’ (res), which is not found in Aristotle but is one of the primary notions
named by Avicenna in his Metaphysics. Thomas’s view on the
relation between the transcendentals ‘being’ (ens) and
‘thing’ is essential for his critique of Avicenna” (Aertsen, Medieval
Philosophy and the Transcendentals, section
4.4., 192).
In
section 3.6. Aertsen explains that the word “accident” in the expression “per se accidents of being” does not refer to the accidents of the categories,
but to the fifth of the Porphyrian predicables. Aertsen, however, indicates
that Aquinas recognized the inappropriateness of the model of predication of a per se accident for conceiving the relation of the other transcendentals to ens. To explain this relationship, Aquinas instead employs the semantic
model of nomen—ratio
significata—res significata. (See Aertsen, 141-146.)
Then in
section 4.5., regarding ens and res, Aertsen continues: “Under the influence of the Arabic philosophy, the
everyday term res acquired a specific philosophical sense in the thirteenth century” (Aertsen, 193).
Preceded by “cf.,” the footnote to this line cites: J. Hamese, “‘Res’ chez les auteurs philosophiques des 12c et 13c siecles ou le passage de la neutralite a la specificite”, in: M. Fattori and M. Bianchi (eds.), Res, IIIo Colloquio Internationale del Lessico Intellectuale Europeo, Rome 1982, pp. 91-104.
Then
Aertsen continues: “’Thing’ is introduced by Thomas in his commentary on Metaphysics IV as a transcendental property in connection with Aristotle’s first
argument for the convertibility of ‘being’ and ‘one.’ This argument,” proceeds
Aertsen, “is that ‘one man’ (unus homo), ‘being man’ (ens homo) and ‘man’ are the same thing, and nothing different is expressed by
repeating the terms (1003b.26 ff.). Thomas is obviously struck by the fact that
Aristotle in his argument speaks not only of ‘being’ and ‘one,’ but also of
‘man.’ He proceeds to give this last concept a transcendental twist through the
notion of ‘thing:’ ‘It should be noted that the name “man” is imposed form the
quiddity or nature of man, and the name “thing” from the quiddity only; but the
name “being” (ens) is imposed from the act of being, and the name “one” (unum) from order or the lack of division, for what is one is undivided
being. What has an essence and a quiddity by reason of that essence, and what
is undivided in itself, are the same. Hence these three—res, ens, and unum —signify absolutely the same but
according to diverse concepts (rationes)’”
(Aertsen, 193).
Footnote: In IV Metaph., lect. 2, 553: “Sciendum est enim quod hoc nomen homo, imponitur a quidditate, sive a natura hominis; et hoc nomen res imponitur a quidditate tantum; hoc vero nomen ens, imponitur ab actu essendi: et hoc nomen unum, ab ordine vel indivisione. Est enim unum ens indivisum. Idem autem est quod habet essentiam et quidditatem per illam essentiam, et quod est in se indivisum. Unde ista tria, res, ens, unum, significant omnino idem, sed secundum diversas rationes.”
“Thomas
introduces a conceptual difference between ‘thing’ and ‘being,’” Aertsen
remarks, “which does not make sense in Aristotle’s metaphysics. The ratio of res is taken from the essence or quiddity, the ratio of ens from the act
of being. Yet they do not signify something that is really different; they
signify the same concretum, which is
called res when it is viewed from its
essence or ‘reality,’ and ens when it
is viewed from its esse or
‘actuality.’ Thomas bases the conceptual difference between ens and res on a real diversity in the structure of that which is. In every
thing two aspects are to be considered, namely, its quiddity and its being (esse). The name res is derived from the first component, the name ens from the second. He attributes this
distinction to Avicenna, not only in his derivation of the transcendentals in De veritate 1.1 but also in other texts”
(Aertsen, 193-194).
Footnote: See In I Sent., 8.1.1; 25.1.4: “secundum Avicennam (…) hoc nomen ‘ens’ et ‘res’ differunt secundum quod est duo considerare in re, scilicet quidditatem et rationem ejus, et esse ipsius.”
“In
reality, however, this attribution obscures the fundamental difference between
the two thinkers” (Aertsen, 194).
“In
Avicenna’s account of the common notions and their differences, ‘thing’ is the
point of departure and has the central place. It signifies the ‘determinate
nature’ (certitudo) through which a
thing is what it is. The term has primarily an ontological sense, as is clear
from Avicenna’s examples. Thus the certitudo
of a triangle is that whereby it is a triangle, that of whiteness that whereby
it is white. The Avicennian sense of certitudo
expresses the Greek tradition of intelligibility, which focuses on the essence
of a thing by posing the question concerning what it is. Res signifies the ‘what-ness’ or quiddity of a thing, which
Avicenna also describes as ‘its proper being’ (esse proprium). The quiddity proper to each thing is something
other (praeter) than esse, although the concept of ens cannot be separated from the concept
of res. It is rather always
concomitant with it, ‘for the thing has being either in the singular or in the
estimation and intellect” (Aertsen, 194).
Footnote: Avicenna, Liber de scientia divina I, 5 (ed. Van Riet, pp. 34-36).
“To
Avicenna ‘thing’ is the primary transcendental; his problem is how the other
common notions, like ‘being,’ can add something to it” (Aertsen,
194).
“That
this interpretation is justified appears from Thomas’s treatment of Avicenna in
his commentary on Metaphysics IV, lect. 2. He observes that according to the
Arabic philosopher, the name ens does
not signify the substance of a thing but something added to it, and he proceeds
to explain the reasons how Avicenna comes to this view. It follows from his
doctrine on creation that every creature has being (esse) from another, and that a thing’s being is thus different from
its substance or essence. Now the name ens
signifies ‘to be’ (esse) and it
therefore seems to signify something added to the essence” (Aertsen,
194-195).
Footnote: In IV Metaph., lect. 2, 556.
“But to
Thomas’s mind this view is incorrect. His argument is:
“Even
though a thing’s esse is different
from its essence, it must not be understood to be something added in the manner
of an accident but something constituted, as it were, by the principles of the
essence. Hence the name ens, which is
imposed (to signify) from esse
itself, signifies the same thing as the name imposed from the essence” (Aertsen,
195).
Footnote: Ibid., lect. 2, 558: “Esse enim rei quamvis sit aliud ab eius essentia, non tamen est intelligendum quod sit aliquod superadditum ad modum accidentis, sed quasi constituitur per principia essentiae. Et ideo hoc nomen ens quod imponitur ab ipso esse, significat idem cum nomine quod imponitur ab ipsa essentia.”
“Thomas’s
argument has not only been criticized by modern scholars; it is also regarded
as contradictory by his own contemporaries” (Aertsen, 195).
Footnote: Cf. K. Flasch, Die Metaphysik des Einen bei Nikolaus von Kues, Leiden 1973, p. 75.
“Siger
of Brabant found Thomas’s position unintelligible (non intelligo). To say that being is not the essence, yet is
constituted by the principles of the essence, is to affirm and to deny the same
thing” (Aertsen, 195).
Footnote: Siger of Brabant, In Metaph., Introduct., q. 7 (ed. Dunphy, p. 45).
“The
formulation of Thomas’s argument is surely not as clear as one might wish. So
he seems to use the term ‘essence’ in
abstracto, that is, as principle, when affirming the real diversity between
esse and essence; and in concreto, that is, as substance, when
affirming that being is constituted by the principles of essence. Yet there can
be no doubt about the intention and meaning of his argument. Thomas’s critics
do not sufficiently take the Avicennian background of the discussion into
account. Avicenna’s problem is how the common terms ‘being’ and ‘one’ can add
something to the primary transcendental ‘thing,’ and his solution is that they
add a real nature to ‘thing’ in the manner of an accident” (Aertsen,
195).
“Thomas
wants to make clear in the first place that the communia are not accidents. He adopts the same strategy when he
engages Avicenna in his commentary on Metaphysics
X. In this text, which also deals with ‘being’ and ‘one,’ Thomas makes a
comparison between communia and
accidents. There exists a similarity between them, because both do not signify
something that subsists. Yet the difference is that communia signify the nature of that which they are said, whereas
accidents signify some nature added above the things of which they are
predicated. This difference was ignored by Avicenna when he posited ‘one’ and ‘being’
as accidental predicates” (Aertsen, 195-196).
Footnote: In X Metaph., lect. 3, 1980: “In hoc enim differunt communia ab accidentibus, quamvis utrisque sit commune non esse hoc aliquid: quia communia significant ipsam naturam suppositorum, non autem accidentia, sed aliquam naturam additam”; 1981: “Hoc autem non considerans Avicenna posuit quod unum et ens sunt praedicata accidentalia, et quod significant naturam additam supra ea de quibus dicuntur.”
“How
can Thomas now show that ens
signifies the same reality as the name imposed from the essence, that is, res? The answer is that he adopts the
Avicennian perspective of the primacy of essence in a way that is not
unfaithful to his own views. Being is received and determined by the essence,
and is in this sense ‘constituted’ by it. In De ente Thomas describes essentia
as that through which and in which ens
has being” (Aertsen, 196).
Footnote: De ente, c. 1: “Sed essentia dicitur secundum quod per eam et in ea ens habet esse.”
“Things
acquire being through their natures. Consequently, ens does not signify another nature than ‘thing’” (Aertsen,
196).
“With
that, however, the most essential has not yet been said. Esse, from which the name ens
is taken, is the very actuality of every essence or nature and, therefore, the
inner principle by which a nature is. The notion of actuality makes clear that
Thomas’s doctrine of the transcendentals has a basis different from Avicenna’s
doctrine of the common notions. ‘Being,’ not ‘thing,’ is the first
transcendental, and this primacy dominates his doctrine. Thomas’s problem is
how the other transcendentals can add something to being” (Aertsen, 196).
“Does
‘thing’ really have a transcendental character in Thomas?” (Aertsen,
196).
Footnote: “On res as transcendental see S. Ducharme, ‘Note sur le transcendental “res” selon Saint Thomas’, in: Revue de l’Universite d’Ottawa 10 (1940), section speciele pp. 85-99; J. Van de Wiele, ‘“Res” en “ding”. Bijdrage tot een vergeiijkende studie van de zijnsopvatting in het Thomisme en bij Heidegger’, in: Tijdschrift voor Filosofie 24 (1962), pp. 427-506. Cf. L. Oeing-Hanhoff, ‘“Res” comme concept transcendental et sur-transcendental’, in: Res, IIIo Colloquio Internationale del Lessico Intellectuale Europeo, Rome 1982, pp. 285-96.
“He
states explicitly in two places that ‘thing’ belongs to the transcendentals (res est de transcendentibus)” (Aertsen, 196).
Footnote: In I Sent., 2.1.5 ad 2; S.th. I, 39.3 ad 3.
“Yet
various authors from Suarez to modern times have denied that res is a separate transcendental, because it is synonymous with ens” (Aertsen, 196).
Footnote: Cf. J. A. Wallace, “Thing”, in: The New Catholic Encyclopedia XIV, San Francisco and Toronto 1967, pp. 91-92.
“This
synonymy is rejected, however, by Thomas. In his commentary on Metaphysics IV
he applies, as we saw, the semantic model of nomen—ratio—res to ‘being’ and ‘thing.’ They signify the same reality but according to
different rationes. Ens and res are not synonyms” (Aertsen, 196-197).
“Thomas
distinguishes two senses of ‘thing.’ The first and primary meaning is
ontological: that is called res which has a determinate and
stable being (esse
ratum et firmum) in nature. This meaning,
it is suggested, derives from the Latin ratus,
‘determinate,’ ‘stable,’ ‘valid.’ According to this meaning res signifies that which has a quiddity or essence, the Avicennian
‘certitude.’ The second meaning is cognitive. Because a thing is knowable
through its essence, the name res is extended to all that is apt
to enter into knowledge. Thomas derives this meaning etymologically from the
verb reor, reris, ‘to think’ or ‘to opine.’ This mode of res can
signify things that have no stable being in nature, such as negations and
privations” (Aertsen, 197).
Footnote: In II Sent., 37.1.1. Cf. In I Sent., 25.1.4. A similar distinction is to be found in Bonaventure, In II Sent. 37, dub. 1 (Opera Omnia II, p. 876).
“The
second mode is more general than the first, transcendental mode, but Thomas
stresses that the extension of the second meaning of ‘thing’ is not greater
than that of ‘being,’ for a ‘thing of reason’ (res rationis) is at
the same time a ‘being of reason’ (ens rationis)” (Aertsen, 197).
“That every
being is a thing implies, on the one hand, that it is fixed and stable through
its essence, and on the other hand, that we are thereby able to ‘think’ the
thing, for it is knowable through its essence. From this the conclusion has
been drawn that to Thomas the transcendental ‘thing’ is of decisive importance
for the intelligibility of being” (Aertsen, 197).
Footnote: J. Van de Wiele, “Le probleme de la verite ontologique dans la philosophie de saint Thomas”, in: Revue philosophiques de Louvain 52 (1954), pp. 557-58.
“But
this interpretation is more Avicennian than Thomistic. For Thomas ens is the ‘first intelligible,’ because a thing is only knowable when it
is in act. Ens does not signify, however, any determinate mode of being. Therefore we
next ask what it is, and consider it as res”
(Aertsen, 197).
“The
convertibility of being and thing plays a role in the discussion about the
ontological status of evil. It is used as an argument against the purely
privative character of evil. Since it is an undeniable fact that there is evil
in the world, evil is a thing and a nature, for being and thing are
convertible. In his reply Thomas does not point to the twofold meaning of res but to that of ens: ‘Being is said in two ways’
(cf. sect. 6.2.). In the first way it signifies the entity of a thing, in the
other the truth of a proposition. Only in the latter sense, when the intellect
states ‘evil is,’ can something that is in itself a privation be regarded as a
being. Thomas explains that ‘being’ is convertible with ‘thing,’ insofar as
‘being’ signifies the entity of a thing, as it is divided by the ten categories”
(Aertsen, 197-198).
Footnote: S.th. I, 48.2 ad 2: “ens dupliciter dicitur. Uno modo, secundum quod significat entitatem rei, prout dividitur per decem praedicamenta, et sic convertitur cum re.” Cf. ScG, III, 8 and 9.
“It is
noteworthy that the categories, the first contractions of being, are related to
being in the sense of ‘thing,’ that is, to being in its quidditative aspect”
(Aertsen, 198).
Footnote: Cf. Quodl. II, 2.1: “Sed verum est quod hoc nomen ens, secundum quod importat rem cui competit huiusmodi esse, sic significat essentiam rei, et dividitur per decem genera.” In IX Metaph., lect. 1, 1769: “ens dividitur uno modo secundum quod dicitur quid, scilicet substantia, aut quantitas, aut qualitas, quod est dividere ens per decem praedicamenta.”
“From a
transcendental perspective, Aristotle’s doctrine of the categories must thus be
seen as a metaphysics that views ‘what is’ as res”
(Aertsen, 198).
“The
peculiarity of ‘thing’ is that it is the only transcendental based on an
element in the complex concept of being itself. Ens is
nothing other than ‘what is’ (quod est). ‘It thus appears to
signify both a thing (rem) by the expression quod and esse by the expression est” (Aertsen, 198).
Footnote: In I Perih., lect. 5.
In his
more recent book on the transcendentals, Aertsen summarizes this reflection
saying that “In the text in the Metaphysics commentary [book IV, lecture
2], as in De veritate [question 1,
article 1, corpus], Aquinas bases the conceptual difference between ens and res on a real complexity in the structure of that which is. In
every thing two principles are to be considered, namely, its quiddity and its
being (esse). The name res is derived
from the first component, the name ens from
the second” (“Thomas Aquinas: A First Model,” in Medieval Philosophy as Transcendental thought: From Philip the
Chancellor (ca. 1225) to Francisco Suárez [Leiden: E. J. Brill, 2012], 224).
Conclusion
Both terms ens and res signify in concreto (and not in
abstracto); both terms ens and res signify the same suppositum.
When the quiddity of an extramental subsisting thing is signified in concreto, that instantiated quiddity is signified as a res, as a suppositum, (i.e., as res quod habet esse ratum et firmum in natura).
likewise when the actus essendi of an extramental subsisting thing is signified in concreto, that instantiated actus essendi is referred to as ens or quod est, i.e., as a suppositum.
When the quiddity of an extramental subsisting thing is signified in concreto, that instantiated quiddity is signified as a res, as a suppositum, (i.e., as res quod habet esse ratum et firmum in natura).
likewise when the actus essendi of an extramental subsisting thing is signified in concreto, that instantiated actus essendi is referred to as ens or quod est, i.e., as a suppositum.
Because extramental subsisting things are composed of quiddity and actus essendi, it is always the case that one and the same extramental subsisting thing is simultaneously habens quidditatem and habens actum essendi.