For a more extensive analysis of text no. 2 than what appears in this post, see my Actus essendi and the Habit of the First Principle in Thomas Aquinas (New York: Einsiedler Press, 2019), 78-82.
Commentary on
In I Sententiarum, distinction 8, question 4, article 2, ad 2
The question asked in this article is whether or not God belongs to the category of substance. In a rather unusual way in this article, Aquinas does not structure his answer in a corpus. Rather, after granting the argument of the second sed contra, Aquinas delivers his own explanation within the segment of the sed contra.
In the second sed contra Aquinas uses the axiom quidquid est in genere habet esse suum
determinatum ad illud genus and the premise that the divine esse transcends all categories—divinum esse nullo modo terminatum est ad
aliquod genus—to conclude that God does not belong to the category of
substance. The explanation of the validity of the sed contra is formulated in four reasons—ratio quadruplex assignatur. Of these, only one argument interests
us here, the ratio subtilior which
Aquinas attributes to Avicenna.
Here is the text:
“Tertia ratio subtilior est
Avicennae. Omne quod est in genere, habet quidditatem differentem ab esse,
sicut homo; humanitati enim ex hoc quod est humanitas, non debetur esse in
actu; potest enim cogitari humanitas et tamen ignorari an aliquis homo sit. Et
ratio hujus est, quia commune, quod praedicatur de his quae sunt in genere,
praedicat quidditatem, cum genus et species praedicentur in eo quod quid est.
Illi autem quidditati non debetur esse nisi per hoc quod suscepta est in hoc
vel in illo. Et ideo quidditas generis vel speciei non communicatur secundum
unum esse omnibus, sed solum secundum unam rationem communem. Unde constat quod
esse suum non est quidditas sua. In Deo autem esse suum est quidditas sua
aliter enim accideret quidditati, et ita esset acquisitum sibi ab alio, et non
haberet esse per essentiam suam. Et ideo Deus non potest esse in aliquo genere”
(In I Sententiarum, distinction 8,
question 4, article 2, sed contra 2).
Aquinas begins by stating that in
everything that belongs to the genus of substance one finds the real
distinction of quidditas and esse. If
one takes for example man—homo, one
does not need to know of the existence of some man to reason conceptually about
the quiddity of man—humanitas.
This is so, Aquinas argues, because the common concept that is predicated of many things in a genus is the quiddity.
A quiddity exists in the real world only when it is received in this or that other individual thing.
Therefore in a genus, the quiddity is not communicated to many individuals according to one esse but according to the consideration of the intellect which considers a nature like that of man, without referring to Socrates and Plato. Thus Plato and Socrates have in common the nature of humanity but the esse of Plato’s humanity and the esse of Socrates’s humanity are numerically different. God, however, does not instantiate a quidditas different from His own esse since, in God, esse actu is His quiddity. God therefore is not in the category of substance.
This is so, Aquinas argues, because the common concept that is predicated of many things in a genus is the quiddity.
A quiddity exists in the real world only when it is received in this or that other individual thing.
Therefore in a genus, the quiddity is not communicated to many individuals according to one esse but according to the consideration of the intellect which considers a nature like that of man, without referring to Socrates and Plato. Thus Plato and Socrates have in common the nature of humanity but the esse of Plato’s humanity and the esse of Socrates’s humanity are numerically different. God, however, does not instantiate a quidditas different from His own esse since, in God, esse actu is His quiddity. God therefore is not in the category of substance.
With this background Aquinas
proceeds to analyze a definition of substance which was used in the second
objection to answer the question in the affirmative. The authority of Avicenna
is invoked again, but according to John F. Wippel the attribution of this definition of
substance to Avicenna is likely to be a quotation ad sensum and not ad litteram,
since the exact text has not been found in Avicenna’s writings. (1) The
definition is this: “substance is that (ens) which does not inhere in a subject, but which exists in itself (ens per se).” And the second objection contends that this definition
applies most fittingly to God. Therefore, God is in the genus of substance.
The
Latin text of the objection reads as follows: “Praeterea, substantia
est quod non est in subjecto, sed est ens per se. Cum igitur Deo hoc maxime
conveniat, videtur quod ipse sit in genere substantiae” (In I Sententiarum, distinction 8, question 4, article 2, objection
2).
In his answer, Aquinas argues
that this definition cannot be the definition of substance because, on the one
hand, ens is not a genus and, on the
other, the negation expressed with the phrase “does not inhere in a subject,” that is, substantia
inquantum praedicatur non ut in subiecto existens, adds nothing that can be considered part of a definition since a pure negation
cannot serve as a genus. It is at this point that Aquinas introduces the term “actus essendi” to accentuate the
contrast between the meaning of the notion of “genus” and the meaning of the
notion of “ens:”
“A genus does not signify esse, a genus signifies the quiddity.”
“Ens does not signify the quiddity, ens signifies the actus
essendi.”
Thus,
when addressing the passage from “ens which does not inhere in a subject”
to “therefore it is in the genus of substance, Aquinas concludes with a simple non
sequitur.
Thus
Aquinas writes in In I
Sententiarum, distinction 8, question 4, article 2, ad 2:
“Ad
secundum dicendum, quod ista definitio, secundum Avicennam, non potest esse
substantiae: substantia est quae non est in subjecto. Ens enim non est genus.
Haec autem negatio ‘non in subjecto’ nihil ponit; unde hoc quod dico, ens non
est in subjecto, non dicit aliquod genus: quia in quolibet genere oportet
significare quidditatem aliquam, ut dictum est, de cujus intellectu non est esse.
Ens autem non dicit quidditatem, sed solum actum essendi, cum sit principium
ipsum; et ideo non sequitur: est non in subjecto: ergo est in genere
substantiae. Sed hoc Deo non convenit, ut dictum est.”
Commenting
on this text J. F. Wippel explains that “Thomas appeals to a point we have
already seen him make in other contexts: whatever is included in a genus must
signify a quiddity which does not include the act of being (esse) in its intelligible content. In
fact, the term being (ens) does not
signify quiddity but rather the act of being (actus essendi). Therefore it does not follow that if something is
not in a subject, it is included in the genus of substance. What does follow is
this. If something has a quiddity to which it belongs to exist not in a subject,
then it is included within the genus of substance. But this (to have a quiddity
to which it belongs to exist not in a subject) is not true of God. Therefore
God does not fall within the genus substance” (The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas, 230).
For
more on the definition of substance see J. F. Wippel, The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas, 228-237; and Jorgen Vijgen, The Status of Eucharistic Accidents “sine subiecto” (Berlin : Akademie Verlag, 2013) 181-184.
Two
things are worth noting regarding the use of the term “actus essendi” in
this passage. First, that the text containing the term “actus essendi” is inserted in a context in which Aquinas is
referring exclusively to the quiddity of the substance, not to the
quiddity of accidents. And more importantly, second, that the three terms “esse,” “ens,” and “actus essendi”
appear in the same text. How do these three terms relate to each other?
Concerning the res significata and the ratio significata of the term
ens, there is no room for doubt.
Aquinas says explicitly that ens non dicit quidditatem sed solum actum essendi. And from the way Aquinas explains the difference
between the notion of “genus” and the notion of “ens,” it is clear also that the ratio significata of the term esse
is the intellectual conception of the actus
essendi, for he says that in quolibet genere oportet significare quidditatem
aliquam de cujus intellectu non est esse.
Thus
in this text again, it is indicated that the three terms “esse,” “ens,” and “actus essendi”
have the same res significata,
namely, the metaphysical principle of actus
essendi. The term “ens” differs
from “esse” and “actus essendi” in that it has a different ratio significata; the term “ens” responds to an intellectual conception of the metaphysical principle of actus essendi that is different from the intellectual conception of the metaphysical principle of actus essendi to which the terms
“esse” and “actus essendi” respond.
Notes
(1) J. F. Wippel writes: “[A]s
Gilson has pointed out in an interesting article, almost from the beginning of
his career Thomas repeatedly returns to a point which he also attributes to
Avicenna: being in itself (per se) is
not the definition of substance. … Gilson has managed to show that there is
some foundation in the Latin translation of Avicenna’s Metaphysics for Thomas to attribute this view to him. Even for this
attribution to be successful, one must concede that “not to be in a subject”
(or better, “to be not in a subject”) can be identified with “to be in itself.”
Gilson’s identification and interpretation of this particular passage from
Avicenna is highly plausible. If correct, it is another illustration of how
likely Thomas was to quote a difficult and possibly confusing text from the
Latin Avicenna ad sensum rather than ad litteram” (The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas [Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America Press, 2000] 229-230).