Entry 0366: Dating of the Texts in which Aquinas
Uses the Expression actus essendi
Aquinas uses the expression actus essendi in four passages in his Quaestiones disputatae De veritate:
Text no. 5: Disputed questions De veritate, question 1, article 1, corpus
Text no. 6: Disputed questions De veritate, question 1, article 1, ad 1.
Text no. 7: Disputed questions De veritate, question 1, article 1, resp. ad s. c. 3.
Text no. 8: Disputed questions De veritate, question 10, article 8, ad 13.
In his doctoral
dissertation, The Philosophical Vocabulary
of Saint Thomas Aquinas in De veritate, James E. Royce explores in greater detail
the evidence that substantiate the assigned date of composition of De veritate. Royce relies on the work
of Henry Denifle (1844-1905) who collected and edited documents referring to the
history of the University
of Paris during the time
of Saint Thomas Aquinas. Here is the entire section “De veritate: Circumstances
and Date of Its Composition” from Royce’s dissertation.
Royce writes:
“Henry Denifle,
O.P., the great authority on documentary sources for the history of the the University of Paris during the time of Saint Thomas Aquinas, makes the remark
in a note in the Chartularium Universitatis Parisiensis that the old lives of Saint Thomas agree about
one date if about nothing else: Saint Thomas was made a magister in theology at the University of Paris in the
year 1256” (Henrious Denifle et Aemilio Chatelain, Chartularium Universitatis Parisiensis,
Delalain, Paris, 1889, I, 307, note 1).
“This is important,
because it clinches beyond all doubt the dating of the Quaestiones disputatae De veritate. Biographers, historians, and critical scholars are in unanimous agreement that the
work was the fruit of his first years of teaching at the University
of Paris ,
immediately after he was advanced to the magisterium.
“The oldest sources for the life of Saint Thomas are in remarkable
agreement on the facts of these years of Saint Thomas 's life
and work. A study of the writings of William of Tocco, Bernard Guido, and Peter Calo
reveals that Saint Thomas
was made licentiate in theology in the early months of 1256, and master later
in that same year.” (See Friedrich Ueberweg, Grundriss
der Geschichte der Philosophie [rev. Bernhard Geyer], Mittler
and Son, Berlin 1928, II, 423. An excellent
bibliography on the life of Saint Thomas Aquinas is contained in P. Mandonnet and J. Destrez, Bibliographie
Thomiste [Bibliotheque Thomiste, I],
Le Saulchoir, Kain, Belgique, 1921, 1-7. More recent is the bibliography found in P. A. Waltz, O.P.,
‘Chronotaxis Vitae et Operum s. Thomae de Aquino,’ Angelicum, 1939, XVI, 463-473. The Bollandists
list the old sources and reproduce many of them, Acta Sanctorum: Martii, I, 655-657).
“Bartholomew, or
Ptolemy, or Tolomey, of Lucca was
a disciple of Saint Thomas
and a church historian who died in the year 1327. In his life of Saint Thomas he
says, ‘Post hoc, ipso magistrato, fecit Questiones De veritate. Post tres annos
magisterii sui redit in Italiam’” (Fide Pierre Mandonnet, O.P., Des Ecrits Authentiques de S. Thomas D'Aquin [2me edition], Saint-Paul, Fribourg, 1910, 59).
“Another early biographer,
Bartholomew of Capua (Logotheta), a Sicilian who as a student followed the lectures
of Saint Thomas, dates the De veritate as being written after Saint Thomas was made master
and during his first period of teaching· at Paris, before going to Italy in 1259”
(Alexander Birkenmajer, ‘Kleinere Thomasfragen,’ Phi1osophisches Jahrbuch, 1921, XXXIV,
32).
“The English Dominican
Nicholas Trevet, who died in 1328, made a catalogue of the works of Saint Thomas between
the years 1319 and 1323, in which he notes that Saint Thomas ‘scripsit etiam primam
partem de Quaestionibus disputatis De veritate et ultra, quas Parisiis disputavit’”
(Mandonnet, Des Ecrits Authentiques,
47-48).
“The older historians,
following these sources, tell us that the young Thomas came to Paris in 1252 from the school of Albert
the Great at Cologne ,
and spent the years 1252-1256 as a bachelor in theology in Paris .
Although they agree that he was made master in 1256, there seems to be good evidence
that the formal inceptio by which he was recognized as a master by the
faculty of the University
of Paris did not take place
until October, 1257. This is the opinion of J. Echard in his life of Saint Thomas. (See Echard-Quetif [Bibliothecae Scriptorum Ordinis Praedicatorum, Paris,
1719-. 1721, I, ad annum 1274], S. Thomae
Aquinatis Opera, Simon Occhi, Venetiis, 1775, I, ix-xxv.) It is also the opinion of the church historian
Fleury; of John Francis Bernard Maria de Rubeis (see Dissertationes Criticae etc. [Pasquali, Venetiis, 1750, Dissertatio
XI, caput ii], S. Thomae Aquinatis Opera [ed. Leonina], Romae, 1882, I, clxxv); and of
Ueberweg (see op. cit., 424). Since
all agree that he left for Italy in 1259, Quaestio I of the De veritate was almost certainly written
in 1257. The editors of the Vives edition, however, say ‘1257 Parisiis… Laurea donatus,
ab anno 1258 ad annum sequentem Questiones De veritate … scripsit’” (Opera Omnia
S. Thomae Aquinatis [ed. Stanislaus
Edward Frette et Paul Mare], Apud Ludovicum Vives, Paris, 1871, I, xii).
“(The fact mentioned
by the Bollandists in the Acta Sanctorum [Martii, I, “Commentarius praevius,”
657b] that Saint Thomas was made doctor of theology in the year 1253, must not be
confused with his being made magister at the University of Paris, for the doctorate
was always previous even to the licentiate in those days, and in this case was probably
granted by the Dominican Order rather than by the University.)”
“The most recent
investigations confirm these conclusions. Dr. Martin Grabmann in his Thomas von Aquin (F. Pustet, Munchen, 1926, 3-5) states that Saint Thomas received his licentiate in 1256 and
left Paris
in 1259, and in his latest work on Die
Werke des Hl. Thomas von Aquin (Aschendorff,
Munster, 1931, 276, 280) he makes these the outside dates for the writing of the De veritate. Pierre Mandonnet in the latest expression of his mind on the subject dates the De veritate I as somewhere in the year 1256-1257. (See S. Thomae Aquinatis Quaestiones disputatae,
Lethielleux, Paris , 1925, ‘Introduction,’ I, 19.
He here summarizes his ‘Chronologie des questions disputes de saint
Thomas d’Aquin,’ Revue Thomiste, 1918, XXIII, 266-287,
341-371.) A most recent summary (1939) of the investigations on the subject lays
down the following chronology:
1252-1256 Parisiis,
Baccalaureus
1256 Obtenta licentia,
fit magister in theologia
1257 a collegiis
magister agnoscitur
1259 in Italiam
rediit
and states that
the disputed questions De veritate date
at the outside from 1256 to 1259. (See Walz, op. cit., 470.) From all this we gather
that it is quite safe to assign the year 1257 as the extremely probable date for
the first question, for it is certain that Saint Thomas was at work on them by that
time and it is highly probable that he at least did not progress very far during
1256.”
“It must be noted
that the controversies which raged for some time in the various European learned
periodicals between Grabmann, J. Koch, Mandonnet, P. Synave, and others regarding
the chronology of the disputed questions does not touch the date of the De veritate at all, but centers rather around the dating
of De Anima, De Spiritualibus Creaturis, and De Unione Verbi Incarnati. A good idea
of these discussions can be obtained from the reviews in the Bulletin Thomiste for 1924 and 1926. (See Bulletin Thomiste, 1924, I, 58-61; III,
1-21 especially.) All the authorities, as well as all of the old catalogues, especially
two ‘book lists’ of the University of Paris dating from 1275-1286 and 1292-1294
respectively, assure us that the De veritate is the first of the disputed
questions of Saint Thomas. (See Denifle-Chatelain, Chart. Univ. Paris, I, 646.)”
“The historical
facts being established, it remains to interpret them in terms of their setting.
The De veritate represents the work of Saint Thomas during
a relatively early period in his productive career. But he was by this time no novice
in the realm of philosophy and theology. He had been commenting on Peter the Lombard 's
books of Sentences since 1252 and had committed the fruits of this
teaching to writing. He had composed some seven or eight small philosophical works,
including the De Ente et Essentia.
He was by then a veteran of the battle which grew out of the antagonism which the
secular clergy and laity of the University of Paris had shown toward the new Order
of Preachers; as his own share in the controversy he had contributed the Contra Impugnantes Dei Cultum et Religionem.
Now with William of Saint Amour condemned and his own Order vindicated by the Pope,
Aquinas began to teach as master of theology in one of the Dominican colleges which
by that time had been incorporated into the University of Paris .
(See J. Echard, Vita Santi Thomae, uses the expression, ‘Pacatis tandem rebus laurea donatus questiones de veritate disputavit
…’ loc. cit., x.)”
“This meant a very
active engagement in the public scholastic life of that violently intellectual atmosphere.
For in the Paris
of that day school meant more than dull classroom routine. In the twelfth
century a question arising out of the interpretation of scripture or some author,
usually Peter the Lombard ,
had formed the basis of the lecture of the master. This easily turned into a discussion
or dispute. The dispute finally detached itself from the lesson and became a separate
exercise in its own right, being known as the ‘ordinary disputation.’ Every master
in theology at Paris
had to put on several of these ordinary disputations a year. According to
Mandonnet and Synave Saint Thomas held them as often as twice a week. Pelster and Birkenmajer disagree with the methods
used to arrive at that conclusion, but only, it would seem, in order to dispute
about the chronology of some of the later Quaestiones disputatae. At any rate, he certainly held them oftener than a few times a year” (see F. Pelster, review of P. Synave, ‘Le Probleme chronologique des questions disputees de S. Thomas d'Aquin,’ Scholastik, 1926, I, 587-590; and of Birkenmajer, see op. cit., 36-45).
"The subject was
fixed in advance, and was usually confined to a single topic although more than
one might be discussed if they were related. All the classes of the other bachelors
and masters ceased for that morning, and we may imagine with what curiosity they
flocked to the disputation hall of the brilliant young disciple of the Aristotelian
Albert, already making a name for himself. At this session, however, the magister only presided; he might summarize and otherwise
help, but the bachelors did the arguing. The next day, or the first day on which
nothing prevented, there followed the magisterial ‘determination,’ the formal recapitulation
and pronouncement of the master upon the subject of the previous disputation. Bachelors
could not ‘determine,’ this being the sole right of the master, though the preliminary
arguments which he presented were usually those proposed by the bachelors the day
before. The Quaestiones disputatae as we have them are the written form, then,
not of the disputation but of the determinatio of the master. (See Hastings Rashdall, The Universities of Europe in the Middle
Ages [new ed. Rev. F. M. Powicke],
Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1936, I, 490-496; Mandonnet, Quaestiones disputatae, ‘Introduction,’
I, 8-15.) Each article of the present form represents one such determination. We
possess 510 of these written by Saint Thomas, of which 253 are under the general title De veritate, though only twelve are included
under the first question which really forms the treatise bearing that name.
"These disputations
with their magisterial determinations gave Saint Thomas a chance to work out at great
length and in a controversial atmosphere much of what he was later to set forth
more positively and succinctly in the two Summas. They do not, it is true, represent
his best period, namely that from 1268 (when he got hold of certain material in
translation from the Greek) until his death in 1274. Yet they do form an important
part of his writings being often his fullest treatment of a topic. The De veritate shows a decisiveness and a firmness of touch
not observed in the commentaries on the Sentences. The problems essayed are difficult,
the manner of their treatment profound and skillful. Since in them historical background
is more prominent than in the Summa theologica, they reflect better the doctrinal milieu in which he was working."