For a more extensive analysis of text no. 8 than what appears in this post, see my Actus essendi and the Habit of the First Principle in Thomas Aquinas (New York: Einsiedler Press, 2019), 120-121.
Commentary on
De veritate, question 10, article 8, ad 13
Aquinas uses the expression actus essendi in one more text in De veritate, in question 10, article 8,
ad 13.
The question asked in this
article is whether the human soul knows itself per essentiam or per speciem.
The question is whether the essence of the human soul is itself that whereby
the human soul knows itself: Et hoc modo ad praesens quaeritur utrum anima per
suam essentiam intelligat se.
One of the difficulties Aquinas
faces in this question is that in order to say that the human soul knows itself
per essentiam, the object known and
that whereby the object is made known have to be identical. If this is not the
case, then that whereby the human soul is made known would have to be something
other than the human soul itself, and therefore the human soul would not be
knowing itself per essentiam.
Here Aquinas reasons that the
form and that which the form informs cannot be the same under the same aspect.
The intellectual faculty, for example, informs the human soul as property to subject. Thus, the potentia intellectiva is an accidental form that inheres in the human soul.
But the human soul cannot in this way be the form of the intellectual faculty.
The relationship between the human soul and the intellective power can then be considered in two ways: (1) in regard to the order of the real, that is to say, quantum ad actum essendi; and (2) in regard to the conceptual order, that is to say, quantum ad actum intelligendi.
The intellectual faculty, for example, informs the human soul as property to subject. Thus, the potentia intellectiva is an accidental form that inheres in the human soul.
But the human soul cannot in this way be the form of the intellectual faculty.
The relationship between the human soul and the intellective power can then be considered in two ways: (1) in regard to the order of the real, that is to say, quantum ad actum essendi; and (2) in regard to the conceptual order, that is to say, quantum ad actum intelligendi.
With reference to the actus essendi, the essence of the human
soul cannot be said to be an intelligible form that informs the possible
intellect directly. But in the order of understanding, the human soul can be
made the object of knowledge.
Aquinas distinguishes four ways
in which the human soul can be made the object of knowledge: the first is knowledge
of the human soul in answer to the question an est in the habitual mode; the
second is knowledge of the human soul in answer to the question an est in the
actual mode; the third is knowledge of the quiddity of the human soul by way of
apprehension; and the fourth is knowledge of the quiddity of the human soul by
way of judgment.
The last three ways of knowing the human soul are accomplished per speciem.
The last three ways of knowing the human soul are accomplished per speciem.
Only in the first way of knowing,
that is to say, in answering to the question an est in the habitual mode, can the human soul
be said to directly know itself through its essence.
Aquinas illustrates this with the example of one’s own awareness of being alive: “No one has ever made the mistake of not perceiving that he was alive, a fact which belongs to the knowledge by which one knows in its singularity what goes on in his soul. It is according to this knowledge that the soul is said to be habitually known through its essence” (De veritate, question 10, article 8, ad 2, Rome: Leonine edition, 1970, vol. 22, fasc. 2/1, p. 323 column A, lines 335-341: “Ad secundum dicendum quod nullus unquam erravit in hoc quod non perciperet se vivere, quod pertinet ad cognitionem qua aliquis singulariter cognoscit quid in anima sua agatur; secundum quam cognitionem dictum est quod anima per essentiam suam cognoscitur in habitu.”).
Aquinas illustrates this with the example of one’s own awareness of being alive: “No one has ever made the mistake of not perceiving that he was alive, a fact which belongs to the knowledge by which one knows in its singularity what goes on in his soul. It is according to this knowledge that the soul is said to be habitually known through its essence” (De veritate, question 10, article 8, ad 2, Rome: Leonine edition, 1970, vol. 22, fasc. 2/1, p. 323 column A, lines 335-341: “Ad secundum dicendum quod nullus unquam erravit in hoc quod non perciperet se vivere, quod pertinet ad cognitionem qua aliquis singulariter cognoscit quid in anima sua agatur; secundum quam cognitionem dictum est quod anima per essentiam suam cognoscitur in habitu.”).
The conclusion of the analysis is
that although the human soul can in some fashion know itself directly through
its essence, ordinarily the human soul knows itself per speciem.
Regarding the use of the
expression actus essendi in this
article, here is Aquinas in his own words:
Obejction 13:
Praeterea, non potest idem (esse)
forma et formatum respectu eiusdem; sed intellectus, cum sit quaedam potentia
animae, est quasi quaedam forma essentiae ipsius; ergo non potest esse quod
essentia animae sit forma intellectus, sed id quo aliquid intelligitur est
forma intellectus; ergo mens non videt se ipsam per essentiam suam. (Rome:
Leonine edition, 1970, vol. 22, fasc. 2/1, p. 319 Column B, line 87 - p. 320
column A, line 94).
Answer to the objection:
Answer to the objection:
Ad tertium decimum dicendum quod
intellectiva potentia est forma ipsius animae quantum ad actum essendi eo quod
habet esse in anima sicut proprietas in subiecto; sed quantum ad actum
intelligendi nihil prohibet esse e converso. (Rome: Leonine edition, 1970, vol.
22, fasc. 2/1, p. 324 column A, lines
412-417).
Of the thirteen texts in which
Aquinas explicitly uses the expression actus essendi, the present text (De veritate, question 10, article 8, ad 13) is the only one in which the
expression actus essendi seems at
first to refer to something other than the actus essendi of a subsisting thing that exists in the real world. From the
context, however, there is no question that Aquinas is not introducing a
modification of his understanding of the doctrine of the real distinction between
actus essendi and quod est. The part of the statement that contains the expression actus
essendi should be read as saying “quantum ad actum essendi [animae.]”
The res significata of the expression actus essendi is clarified by indicating that the esse of the potentia intellectiva is the esse
of a proprietas in subiecto. Aquinas
teaches that in the real world, only a subsisting subject possesses esse in the sense of actus essendi.
Accordingly, in the answer to the previous objection (in De veritate, question 10, article 8, ad 12) Aquinas remarks that the quo est that belongs to the human soul is what he calls actus entis. For Aquinas, the human soul is indeed a subsisting subject in which a real distinction and a real composition of quo est (understood as actus essendi) and quod est (understood as the subsisting subject which possesses the actus essendi) is found.
Accordingly, in the answer to the previous objection (in De veritate, question 10, article 8, ad 12) Aquinas remarks that the quo est that belongs to the human soul is what he calls actus entis. For Aquinas, the human soul is indeed a subsisting subject in which a real distinction and a real composition of quo est (understood as actus essendi) and quod est (understood as the subsisting subject which possesses the actus essendi) is found.
Here is Aquinas in his own words:
Obejction 12:
Praeterea, posteriora sunt magis
composita prioribus; sed intelligere est posterius quam esse; ergo in
intelligentia animae invenitur maior compositio quam in eius esse; sed in anima
non est idem quod est et quo est; ergo nec in ea est idem quod intelligitur et
quo intelligitur, et sic mens non se videt per suam essentiam. (Rome: Leonine
edition, 1970, vol. 22, fasc. 2/1, p.
319 column B, lines 79-86).
Answer to the objection:
Answer to the objection:
Ad duodecimum dicendum quod quo
intelligitur et quod intelligitur, non hoc modo se habent ad invicem sicut quo
est et quod est: esse enim est actus entis, sed intelligere non est actus eius
quod intelligitur sed intelligentis; unde quo intelligitur comparatur ad
intelligentem sicut quo est ad quod est. Et ideo sicut in anima est aliud quo
est et quod est, ita aliud est quo intelligit, idest potentia intellectiva,
quae est principium actus intelligendi, a sua essentia. Non autem ex hoc
oportet quod species qua intelligitur sit aliud ab eo quod intelligitur. (Rome:
Leonine edition, 1970, vol. 22, fasc. 2/1, p. 323 Column B, line 400 - p. 324
column A, line 411).